Q: How can we debunk the argument from contingency for the existence of God? The hypothesis that this particular universe exists by the necessity of its own nature has also been refuted. [10] “Begging the Question,” Australian Journal of Philosophy, volume 77, no. You would have to admit that his nature COULD have been otherwise. Kreeft applies this analogy to existence. In 1252, Pope Innocent IV authorized them to torture dissenters. The only way out of this conclusion is for you to abandon your assertion that God’s nature is necessary. Tuesday, 11 March 2014 The Argument from Contingency - Refuted As impressive as that may sound to laypersons, philosophers recognize this as a trite statement. Craig’s switch from material to immaterial causes is worse than just a poor practice. Kreeft’s scenario makes sense when speaking of books, but it falls apart when he implies that “existence” is borrowed from past existences, as though existence were a commodity. Only one kind of cause is known: physical cause. Then why make the substitution? Most people probably never notice Craig’s guileful shift from material to immaterial causes. The argument’s conclusion is therefore contained in one of its premises. The apparent tension between these two definitions of contingency is resolved by recognizing definition 1 as speaking in epistemic rather than ontological terms. . [1] + Everything around us—every cloud, every puppy, every puppy poop—is contingent, said Aquinas, meaning that it didn’t have to exist; some … Your email address will not be published. The posts here describe conversations with Apologists & what I regard as their fallacious arguments. An immaterial cause might be transient or impermanent. Still, using a word in a context where the audience likely won’t recognize this switching back and forth between meanings is a poor practice. [1] Let's analyze the argument by premise: Premise 1: Every temporally contingent being possibly fails to exist at some time. Granted, it’s more in keeping with our experience than any alternative conjecture, but it’s still conjecture. Evidence for the external causes mentioned in premise 1 is drawn from our success in finding explanations within the natural realm, material explanations translatable into the language of physics. All the word contingent signifies is our ignorance. If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is God (a necessary being). Kreeft’s analogy surreptitiously transfigures this mystery about why anything exists into a presumption that there had to be a first cause. Craig denies equivocating between material and immaterial causes, saying that he meant efficient causes all along. The flock of friars called Dominicans were founded by the Spanish priest Saint Dominic de Guzman in France to preach against heresy. Once we understand that premise 1 refers to efficient causes, it’s obvious that premise 1 presupposes immaterial causation. Sometimes contingency is used in the sense of “it … I for one do not know if there is a logical incoherency in God or not, and so I withhold judgment. That inspired me to write up a refutation of the argument, and I'm happy to present it here. It is a form of argument from universal causation. Your email address will not be published. The argument from contingency is, ironically enough, sort of like an argument—I mean the structure of an argument. Since I found this abundance of material causes, there must be an immaterial cause!”, Craig, after relying solely on material causes to establish premise 1, suddenly switches to immaterial causes in premise 2, without alerting his audience that he’s made this switch. Given that all evidence supporting premise 1 consists of material causes, we might be tempted to conclude that, no matter how far back we look in the chain of causation, we will always find another material cause. All Craig is doing here is defining the material realm to include all material causes. [7] A formal fallacy is an error in the logic of an argument that is visible in the form of the argument: how the argument’s premises and conclusion are laid out. The argument from contingency is easily refuted when you remember Plantinga's ontological argument. Craig’s argument not only exploits deceptive wordplay, but it also incorporates fallacious logic. Here is the false premise: “God is an omnipotent being, who can do anything that is logically possible.” The reliance of the argument on this false premise makes the argument itself invalid. For those who came in late, the argument from contingency attempts to establish the necessity of a god given the idea that the universe is contingent on a god, that is, that the universe couldn’t exist without one. Argument from contingency. Wherever there are two possibilities, something must determine which of those possibilities is realized. We can call that necessary thing God.”, Amy: “Wait. [2] Aquinas does not seem prima facie to be speaking about temporal causal chains, but rather about a dubious ontological hierarchy of efficient causes. Don't be caught refuting old arguments - Robert E. Maydole's Temporal Contingency argument for God. Right? Whatever credibility premise 1 has is owed strictly to our experience of material causes. The Argument from Contingency The Argument from Contingency is one of the strongest arguments for the existence of God. [5] Craig often says his premises as “more probably true than false,” and that, this being so, we should embrace his conclusion. We can’t infer immaterial causes from having observed only material causes. To commit oneself to this conjecture would be a mistake. Extrapolating outside the relevant domain is an error well-understood by statisticians studying phenomena within the natural realm. Reply Delete Premise 4 commits this blunder in the worst imaginable way by assuming that we can extrapolate from premise 1 to draw conclusions beyond the natural realm. Craig’s approach, if adopted by a door-to-door salesman, would be classified by the legal profession as a bait and switch scam. The argument from contingency cannot be repudiated by some scientific finding in the future. This is a strength with the Leibnizian Cosmological Argument (also known as The Argument From … For more information, please visit www.religionrefuted.com. [6] Though Craig claims (falsely, I would argue) that he has arguments that prove the immaterial cause is a personal god, substituting “God” for “immaterial” still renders the form of his argument invalid. Craig smuggles in a portrait of Divinity by using the heavily freighted term God.[6]+. I shall then offer an explanation as to why Kant thought he needed a refutation such as this at all. You would have to admit that his nature COULD have been otherwise. Although in Western philosophy the earliest formulation of a versionof the cosmological argument is found in Plato’s Laws,893–96, the classical argument is firmly rooted inAristotle’s Physics (VIII, 4–6) andMetaphysics (XII, 1–6). As far as we know, there are no immaterial entities. [Variation of the Principle of Sufficient Reason.] To say that an entity is contingent can be interpreted to mean (1) the entity is physically possible but not necessary, or (2) the entity is causally dependent on something outside itself. It had to be something within his mind.”, Amy: “There was something about the nature of God’s mind that caused his decision?”, Bob: “Right. That’s sheer conjecture. The Ontological Argument. I would like … What I mean is the argument for contingency can only tell us that there exists what it takes for anything to exist, and that thing is God, but it doesn’t tell us whether that God is the God of Christianity or Judaism or Islam, for example. [3] Bruce Reichenbach, The Cosmological Argument: A Reassessment, Charles Thomas, Springfield,1972, p. 102. www.plato.stanford.edu/entries/cosmological-argument, [4] Peter Kreeft, “Rationality of Belief in God”, 12/25/10, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=yK_71C3C-30. That’s one of the primary responses to Leibniz’s Contingency Argument: the universe is a brute fact — it just is. That’s not always the case. Everything that exists has an explanation of its existence (either in the necessity of its own nature or in an external cause). I’m thinking about getting a tattoo that says that. Wherever there are two possibilities, something must determine which of those … Using definition 1, to say B is contingent is to say that we couldn’t predict with confidence the identity or existence of its causal antecedents. Imagine a believer (Bob) and atheist (Amy) discussing the contingency argument. The most common arg… 4. Premise 2 says, “If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is God.” Note that Craig has substituted the term “God” for “immaterial cause.” When challenged on the legitimacy of this substitution, Craig shrugs that these two terms are equivalent. It’s logical legerdemain. Kant's refutation of the ontological argument-which states that from the concept of a being containing every perfection it is possible to infer its existence-is well known: "In whatever manner the understanding may have arrived at a concept, the existence of its object is never, by any process of … Let’s get real. The most heavily debated aspects of Leibniz’s contingency argument are premises 1 … The acorn might have been eaten by a squirrel. In other words, definition 1 concerns what we know, whereas definition 2 deals with objects out in the real world. There are a lot of good arguments against atheism (like the argument from contingency).There are also some good ones which unfortunately have been used incorrectly so many times that they have been misidentified as bad ones (like Pascal’s Wager).Even more unfortunately, there are also some genuinely bad ones (like the argument from the banana), and some of these are quite popular. Using definition 2, when we say that B is contingent on A, we mean that A causes B. 1. For those among us who would hope that God’s defenders would not deliberately employ intellectual sleight-of-hand, this is a sad spectacle. On what grounds is thisassumption made? [1]+ Everything around us—every cloud, every puppy, every puppy poop—is contingent, said Aquinas, meaning that it didn’t have to exist; some cause made it exist. Let me emphasize that these explanations, these physical causes, are invariably found within the natural realm. It’s possible that the material realm has no cause, that material causes stretch back infinitely or to the beginning. For example, suppose I said to you, “Yesterday I saw a huge boa and took a fancy to it. The Modal Cosmological Argument, also known as the Argument from Contingency, suggests that because the universe might not have existed (i.e. Premise 1’s being about efficient causes raises problems for Craig’s argument. Dr. Craig told me that the Kalam Argument is weakened in its persuasive force on a b-theory, but it isn’t refuted. In other words, B is an inevitable consequence of A. But what if I snickered and told you that I meant snake in the first sentence and stole in the second? They engage with the public to spread Catholicism. From the The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, a newer generation of philosophical arguments have been released to apologists. Grow Successful Recommended for you Critics understandably accuse Craig of committing the informal fallacy known as equivocating.[7]+. It is impossible for science to show that universe can exist in every possible world, because possible worlds are not actual. So now you believe in God, right?”, Amy: “Not so fast! Craig simply presumes the plausibility of immaterial causation, even though no immaterial cause has ever been identified or even adequately defined. Deriving the conclusion requires a conjunction of premises, as opposed to a direct reading of one premise. I might be talking about a snake. One might say, for instance, that a child’s guardian angel was the efficient cause of the child’s stepping onto the sidewalk just in time to avoid a speeding car. As I see it, the argument from contingency simple says that something had to, necessarily, exist in order for all that now exists to exist. If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is … If there’s a chain of causation from A to Z, then Z is inevitable if any preceding entity in the causal chain is inevitable. but the universe is not itself a necessary explanation of its existence. Theists regularly talk about a place "beyond" the universe, a transcendent realm where God exists "outside of time."". Leibniz wrote about many subjects in natural theology and philosophy of religion, including the problem of evil, the cosmological argument… This is a pretty long post, but I think it's no more than such an important subject deserves. The formal argument comes in many forms, so here for instance is the one William Lane Craig uses in his book … Using the term “efficient boa,” I could argue as follows: We have seen efficient boas (by which I mean snakes) within the park; therefore, an efficient boa (by which I mean a stole) exists outside the park. [3] What does it mean, however, to say something is contingent? Clearly this is a claim that God exists in *something*, whatever that something may be, and that the something that God exists in is not identical with … Pope Gregory IX authorized the Dominicans to carry out the Inquisition. Friday, 11 October 2013 Argument from Time and Contingency - Refuted / Leibniz’s Contingency Argument / Everything that exists has an explanation of its existence (either in the necessity of its own nature or in an external cause). Amy: “No. Amy: “Why not? Craig demonstrates with this argument that if the material realm has a cause, it must be immaterial. reason why this or that has happene… The posts here describe conversations with Apologists & what I regard as their fallacious arguments. The heart of the argument is the denial of true contingency. Reply Delete it is contingent, as opposed to necessary), we then need some explanation of why it does exist. His disjunctive syllogism is a hand-waving distraction from this reality. And your whole contingency argument … The philosopher Walter Sinnott-Armstrong puts it this way: “…to avoid begging the question, one’s reason to believe the premise must be independent of both (a) one’s belief in the conclusion and also (b) one’s reason to believe the conclusion.”[10]. [1] A friar dresses in a cloak, much like a monk, but friars don’t stay tucked away in monasteries. [8] If we accept that defense, and I do, then Craig isn’t guilty of equivocating. My argument argues that the Argument from Contingency is sound. Craig engages in precisely this sort of wordplay. The Argument from Contingency Copleston sets out his argument for the existence of God - an argument from contingency that is a type of Cosmological Argument. It seems that Reichenbach is using the term contingent ontologically, per definition 2, asserting that each entity has a cause outside itself. false. All it means is this: if both material and immaterial causes exist, and if we filter out all material causes, we’re left with only immaterial causes. He has free will. But the conclusion is, in Craig’s words “All the more obvious on an A-theory than on a B-theory”. It was God’s nature, just the way his mind works, that led to his decision to create the universe.”, Amy: “Let me get this straight. In a valid deductive argument, the conclusion is derived by combining the logic of the various premises. In support of premise 2, Craig points out that if a cause is a material cause then it is, itself, part of the material realm. If the critic seeks to deny premise #1, this would be an absurdity, since it would mean the universe is eternally self existent, which is refuted by science, including such principles as the 2nd Law of Thermodynamics, and the expansion of the universe. That seems incontrovertible. Critics of the argument from contingency have sometimes questioned whether the universe is contingent, but it remains at least plausible to think that it is so. Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment. As the philosopher Willard Van Orman Quine observed, physical necessity and contingency are empty terms; there is only what is. Craig is pulling a fast one. The Christian philosopher Bruce Reichenbach, like Aquinas, argued that if every part of a whole is contingent, then the whole must be contingent. 3. Denzel Washington's Life Advice Will Leave You SPEECHLESS |LISTEN THIS EVERYDAY AND CHANGE YOUR LIFE - Duration: 10:18. I might be talking about a fluffy pink stole made of ostrich feathers. Friday, 11 October 2013 Argument from Time and Contingency - Refuted Craig’s crafty (though futile) effort to slither a course between these two fallacies demonstrates that he is mindful of his predicament. Whichever I’m talking about, I should try to be clear. Contingency Argument. To say that something is contingent means that it is not necessary. It couldn’t have been any other way.”, Amy: “Why not? This is probably the most important passage in … It is the belief that "everything happens for a reason", that there is actually sufficient (and, indeed, good!) I shall show in this paper that this refutation, while it is frequently taken to be valid,' is in fact fallacious. The structure of an argument goes from initial premise to conclusion. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gtfVds8Kn4s. Definition 1 emphasizes our uncertainty about whether the contingent entity will exist: the entity’s existence is conditional. Yet these efficient causes could be implemented, as far as we know, only by force carrier particles that cannot exceed the speed of light and would therefore manifest as a temporal causal chain. . (So-called final causes are more accurately identified as motives.) Peter Kreeft presents the contingency argument by way of a homey analogy. Science can only show what happens in the actual world. We all know that God is taken by most people in Craig’s audience to be a conscious being, whereas “immaterial cause,” to the extent that it has meaning, doesn’t imply any such thing. Yet Craig commits himself to a far more extravagant conjecture and thereby makes a far more egregious mistake by saying that premise 1 supports the speculation that the cosmos has an immaterial cause. You would probably think I was being purposely deceitful. The efficient cause of the painter’s sunburn was a defect in her sunscreen. My writing differs from Aquinas’s writing not only in volume, but also in tone. It makes no sense to cry out, “Ooh, I found a material cause! It is based on a false premise. Otherwise, all deductive arguments would be fallacious. Craig is arguing that if there’s a cause of M, then (1) M or Not-M is the cause, (2) M is not the cause; therefore, Not-M is the cause. No, I’m not. Aquinas, a member of this order, spent most of his life writing an estimated 8 to 11 million words. Craig himself, in defense of premise 1, provides examples only of material causes, never of immaterial causes. But if you say God’s nature is contingent on something else, then God is a contingent entity. The analogy’s exploitation of scientific illiteracy exemplifies a much broader principle manifest throughout apologetics: Every argument for the supernatural realm is rooted in ignorance of the natural realm. The argument against the existence of God offered by this gentleman is not a valid one. A lot of people conflate the argument from contingency with the so-called “cosmological” argument (a.k.a. That something must not have been a contingent thing, but a necessary thing. An informal fallacy, in contrast, can’t be detected by examining the structure of the argument. The debate starts with a lengthy discussion of the Cosmological Argument.Copleston presents a version of the argument based on contingency, which is based on Aquinas' 'Third Way' and Leibniz's Principle of Sufficient Reason.Russell responds by questioning whether necessary existence (aseity) is a … Sometimes it’s called petitio principii or circular reasoning. What we call today the Kalam Cosmological Argument, was first made by Aristotle and then by Islamic scholars in the 9th century. The conclusion of his argument (statement 5) is that immaterial causation (God) exists. Therefore, the universe has an explanation of its existence (from 1 and 3). Craig, however, doesn’t want to talk only about material causes. it is contingent, as opposed to necessary), we then need some explanation of why it does exist. The Modal Cosmological Argument, also known as the Argument from Contingency, suggests that because the universe might not have existed (i.e. In other words, if we trace back through all the causes within the material realm, and if we encounter the very first material cause, which we can call M, then if we find the cause of M, that cause must be immaterial. Explain the premises of the argument of contingency. The first argument that I would like to consider with you is the argument from contingency. To the pragmatic atheistmany of these arguments remain unpersuasive, ranging from defining something into existence, to at best arguing for some form of … Craig is mired in a catch-22 predicament. For perspective, 10 million words is equivalent to over 60 books the size of the one you’re reading now. The posts here describe conversations with Apologists & what I regard as their fallacious arguments. True, but so is God. Notice that the weakness of this argument would be less apparent if I strike all references to efficient boas, snakes, and stoles and use only the word boas, by which I still mean efficient boas: We have seen boas within the park; therefore, boas exist outside the park. Craig is speaking of the Kalām argument, not contingency argument, but the objections and defenses largely overlap. From the The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, a newer generation of philosophical arguments have been released to apologists. But if you say God’s nature is contingent on something else, then God is a contingent entity. That tells us nothing of theological significance. The argument against the existence of God offered by this gentleman is not a valid one. I've been thinking more and more about the Cosmological Argument lately and I noticed there was a recent thread on it in this forum. All Rights Reserved. Cosrx Salicylic Acid Daily Gentle Cleanser Review,
Bdm Main Quest,
Marvel Premiere Featuring Iron Fist,
Millet Ski Pants,
Baby Gherkin Pickles,
Insurance Sales Agents Salary,
Whale Template Sewing,
Calea Chocolate Cake Recipe,
Nivea Express Hydration Body Lotion 400ml,
Project Portfolio Example For Interview,
Makita Circular Saw Parts Diagram,
Nikon P1000 Bird Photography,
Heinz Seriously Good Mayonnaise,
Esper Stoneblade Legacy,
" />
Q: How can we debunk the argument from contingency for the existence of God? The hypothesis that this particular universe exists by the necessity of its own nature has also been refuted. [10] “Begging the Question,” Australian Journal of Philosophy, volume 77, no. You would have to admit that his nature COULD have been otherwise. Kreeft applies this analogy to existence. In 1252, Pope Innocent IV authorized them to torture dissenters. The only way out of this conclusion is for you to abandon your assertion that God’s nature is necessary. Tuesday, 11 March 2014 The Argument from Contingency - Refuted As impressive as that may sound to laypersons, philosophers recognize this as a trite statement. Craig’s switch from material to immaterial causes is worse than just a poor practice. Kreeft’s scenario makes sense when speaking of books, but it falls apart when he implies that “existence” is borrowed from past existences, as though existence were a commodity. Only one kind of cause is known: physical cause. Then why make the substitution? Most people probably never notice Craig’s guileful shift from material to immaterial causes. The argument’s conclusion is therefore contained in one of its premises. The apparent tension between these two definitions of contingency is resolved by recognizing definition 1 as speaking in epistemic rather than ontological terms. . [1] + Everything around us—every cloud, every puppy, every puppy poop—is contingent, said Aquinas, meaning that it didn’t have to exist; some … Your email address will not be published. The posts here describe conversations with Apologists & what I regard as their fallacious arguments. An immaterial cause might be transient or impermanent. Still, using a word in a context where the audience likely won’t recognize this switching back and forth between meanings is a poor practice. [1] Let's analyze the argument by premise: Premise 1: Every temporally contingent being possibly fails to exist at some time. Granted, it’s more in keeping with our experience than any alternative conjecture, but it’s still conjecture. Evidence for the external causes mentioned in premise 1 is drawn from our success in finding explanations within the natural realm, material explanations translatable into the language of physics. All the word contingent signifies is our ignorance. If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is God (a necessary being). Kreeft’s analogy surreptitiously transfigures this mystery about why anything exists into a presumption that there had to be a first cause. Craig denies equivocating between material and immaterial causes, saying that he meant efficient causes all along. The flock of friars called Dominicans were founded by the Spanish priest Saint Dominic de Guzman in France to preach against heresy. Once we understand that premise 1 refers to efficient causes, it’s obvious that premise 1 presupposes immaterial causation. Sometimes contingency is used in the sense of “it … I for one do not know if there is a logical incoherency in God or not, and so I withhold judgment. That inspired me to write up a refutation of the argument, and I'm happy to present it here. It is a form of argument from universal causation. Your email address will not be published. The argument from contingency is, ironically enough, sort of like an argument—I mean the structure of an argument. Since I found this abundance of material causes, there must be an immaterial cause!”, Craig, after relying solely on material causes to establish premise 1, suddenly switches to immaterial causes in premise 2, without alerting his audience that he’s made this switch. Given that all evidence supporting premise 1 consists of material causes, we might be tempted to conclude that, no matter how far back we look in the chain of causation, we will always find another material cause. All Craig is doing here is defining the material realm to include all material causes. [7] A formal fallacy is an error in the logic of an argument that is visible in the form of the argument: how the argument’s premises and conclusion are laid out. The argument from contingency is easily refuted when you remember Plantinga's ontological argument. Craig’s argument not only exploits deceptive wordplay, but it also incorporates fallacious logic. Here is the false premise: “God is an omnipotent being, who can do anything that is logically possible.” The reliance of the argument on this false premise makes the argument itself invalid. For those who came in late, the argument from contingency attempts to establish the necessity of a god given the idea that the universe is contingent on a god, that is, that the universe couldn’t exist without one. Argument from contingency. Wherever there are two possibilities, something must determine which of those possibilities is realized. We can call that necessary thing God.”, Amy: “Wait. [2] Aquinas does not seem prima facie to be speaking about temporal causal chains, but rather about a dubious ontological hierarchy of efficient causes. Don't be caught refuting old arguments - Robert E. Maydole's Temporal Contingency argument for God. Right? Whatever credibility premise 1 has is owed strictly to our experience of material causes. The Argument from Contingency The Argument from Contingency is one of the strongest arguments for the existence of God. [5] Craig often says his premises as “more probably true than false,” and that, this being so, we should embrace his conclusion. We can’t infer immaterial causes from having observed only material causes. To commit oneself to this conjecture would be a mistake. Extrapolating outside the relevant domain is an error well-understood by statisticians studying phenomena within the natural realm. Reply Delete Premise 4 commits this blunder in the worst imaginable way by assuming that we can extrapolate from premise 1 to draw conclusions beyond the natural realm. Craig’s approach, if adopted by a door-to-door salesman, would be classified by the legal profession as a bait and switch scam. The argument from contingency cannot be repudiated by some scientific finding in the future. This is a strength with the Leibnizian Cosmological Argument (also known as The Argument From … For more information, please visit www.religionrefuted.com. [6] Though Craig claims (falsely, I would argue) that he has arguments that prove the immaterial cause is a personal god, substituting “God” for “immaterial” still renders the form of his argument invalid. Craig smuggles in a portrait of Divinity by using the heavily freighted term God.[6]+. I shall then offer an explanation as to why Kant thought he needed a refutation such as this at all. You would have to admit that his nature COULD have been otherwise. Although in Western philosophy the earliest formulation of a versionof the cosmological argument is found in Plato’s Laws,893–96, the classical argument is firmly rooted inAristotle’s Physics (VIII, 4–6) andMetaphysics (XII, 1–6). As far as we know, there are no immaterial entities. [Variation of the Principle of Sufficient Reason.] To say that an entity is contingent can be interpreted to mean (1) the entity is physically possible but not necessary, or (2) the entity is causally dependent on something outside itself. It had to be something within his mind.”, Amy: “There was something about the nature of God’s mind that caused his decision?”, Bob: “Right. That’s sheer conjecture. The Ontological Argument. I would like … What I mean is the argument for contingency can only tell us that there exists what it takes for anything to exist, and that thing is God, but it doesn’t tell us whether that God is the God of Christianity or Judaism or Islam, for example. [3] Bruce Reichenbach, The Cosmological Argument: A Reassessment, Charles Thomas, Springfield,1972, p. 102. www.plato.stanford.edu/entries/cosmological-argument, [4] Peter Kreeft, “Rationality of Belief in God”, 12/25/10, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=yK_71C3C-30. That’s one of the primary responses to Leibniz’s Contingency Argument: the universe is a brute fact — it just is. That’s not always the case. Everything that exists has an explanation of its existence (either in the necessity of its own nature or in an external cause). I’m thinking about getting a tattoo that says that. Wherever there are two possibilities, something must determine which of those … Using definition 1, to say B is contingent is to say that we couldn’t predict with confidence the identity or existence of its causal antecedents. Imagine a believer (Bob) and atheist (Amy) discussing the contingency argument. The most common arg… 4. Premise 2 says, “If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is God.” Note that Craig has substituted the term “God” for “immaterial cause.” When challenged on the legitimacy of this substitution, Craig shrugs that these two terms are equivalent. It’s logical legerdemain. Kant's refutation of the ontological argument-which states that from the concept of a being containing every perfection it is possible to infer its existence-is well known: "In whatever manner the understanding may have arrived at a concept, the existence of its object is never, by any process of … Let’s get real. The most heavily debated aspects of Leibniz’s contingency argument are premises 1 … The acorn might have been eaten by a squirrel. In other words, definition 1 concerns what we know, whereas definition 2 deals with objects out in the real world. There are a lot of good arguments against atheism (like the argument from contingency).There are also some good ones which unfortunately have been used incorrectly so many times that they have been misidentified as bad ones (like Pascal’s Wager).Even more unfortunately, there are also some genuinely bad ones (like the argument from the banana), and some of these are quite popular. Using definition 2, when we say that B is contingent on A, we mean that A causes B. 1. For those among us who would hope that God’s defenders would not deliberately employ intellectual sleight-of-hand, this is a sad spectacle. On what grounds is thisassumption made? [1]+ Everything around us—every cloud, every puppy, every puppy poop—is contingent, said Aquinas, meaning that it didn’t have to exist; some cause made it exist. Let me emphasize that these explanations, these physical causes, are invariably found within the natural realm. It’s possible that the material realm has no cause, that material causes stretch back infinitely or to the beginning. For example, suppose I said to you, “Yesterday I saw a huge boa and took a fancy to it. The Modal Cosmological Argument, also known as the Argument from Contingency, suggests that because the universe might not have existed (i.e. Premise 1’s being about efficient causes raises problems for Craig’s argument. Dr. Craig told me that the Kalam Argument is weakened in its persuasive force on a b-theory, but it isn’t refuted. In other words, B is an inevitable consequence of A. But what if I snickered and told you that I meant snake in the first sentence and stole in the second? They engage with the public to spread Catholicism. From the The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, a newer generation of philosophical arguments have been released to apologists. Grow Successful Recommended for you Critics understandably accuse Craig of committing the informal fallacy known as equivocating.[7]+. It is impossible for science to show that universe can exist in every possible world, because possible worlds are not actual. So now you believe in God, right?”, Amy: “Not so fast! Craig simply presumes the plausibility of immaterial causation, even though no immaterial cause has ever been identified or even adequately defined. Deriving the conclusion requires a conjunction of premises, as opposed to a direct reading of one premise. I might be talking about a snake. One might say, for instance, that a child’s guardian angel was the efficient cause of the child’s stepping onto the sidewalk just in time to avoid a speeding car. As I see it, the argument from contingency simple says that something had to, necessarily, exist in order for all that now exists to exist. If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is … If there’s a chain of causation from A to Z, then Z is inevitable if any preceding entity in the causal chain is inevitable. but the universe is not itself a necessary explanation of its existence. Theists regularly talk about a place "beyond" the universe, a transcendent realm where God exists "outside of time."". Leibniz wrote about many subjects in natural theology and philosophy of religion, including the problem of evil, the cosmological argument… This is a pretty long post, but I think it's no more than such an important subject deserves. The formal argument comes in many forms, so here for instance is the one William Lane Craig uses in his book … Using the term “efficient boa,” I could argue as follows: We have seen efficient boas (by which I mean snakes) within the park; therefore, an efficient boa (by which I mean a stole) exists outside the park. [3] What does it mean, however, to say something is contingent? Clearly this is a claim that God exists in *something*, whatever that something may be, and that the something that God exists in is not identical with … Pope Gregory IX authorized the Dominicans to carry out the Inquisition. Friday, 11 October 2013 Argument from Time and Contingency - Refuted / Leibniz’s Contingency Argument / Everything that exists has an explanation of its existence (either in the necessity of its own nature or in an external cause). Amy: “No. Amy: “Why not? Craig demonstrates with this argument that if the material realm has a cause, it must be immaterial. reason why this or that has happene… The posts here describe conversations with Apologists & what I regard as their fallacious arguments. The heart of the argument is the denial of true contingency. Reply Delete it is contingent, as opposed to necessary), we then need some explanation of why it does exist. His disjunctive syllogism is a hand-waving distraction from this reality. And your whole contingency argument … The philosopher Walter Sinnott-Armstrong puts it this way: “…to avoid begging the question, one’s reason to believe the premise must be independent of both (a) one’s belief in the conclusion and also (b) one’s reason to believe the conclusion.”[10]. [1] A friar dresses in a cloak, much like a monk, but friars don’t stay tucked away in monasteries. [8] If we accept that defense, and I do, then Craig isn’t guilty of equivocating. My argument argues that the Argument from Contingency is sound. Craig engages in precisely this sort of wordplay. The Argument from Contingency Copleston sets out his argument for the existence of God - an argument from contingency that is a type of Cosmological Argument. It seems that Reichenbach is using the term contingent ontologically, per definition 2, asserting that each entity has a cause outside itself. false. All it means is this: if both material and immaterial causes exist, and if we filter out all material causes, we’re left with only immaterial causes. He has free will. But the conclusion is, in Craig’s words “All the more obvious on an A-theory than on a B-theory”. It was God’s nature, just the way his mind works, that led to his decision to create the universe.”, Amy: “Let me get this straight. In a valid deductive argument, the conclusion is derived by combining the logic of the various premises. In support of premise 2, Craig points out that if a cause is a material cause then it is, itself, part of the material realm. If the critic seeks to deny premise #1, this would be an absurdity, since it would mean the universe is eternally self existent, which is refuted by science, including such principles as the 2nd Law of Thermodynamics, and the expansion of the universe. That seems incontrovertible. Critics of the argument from contingency have sometimes questioned whether the universe is contingent, but it remains at least plausible to think that it is so. Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment. As the philosopher Willard Van Orman Quine observed, physical necessity and contingency are empty terms; there is only what is. Craig is pulling a fast one. The Christian philosopher Bruce Reichenbach, like Aquinas, argued that if every part of a whole is contingent, then the whole must be contingent. 3. Denzel Washington's Life Advice Will Leave You SPEECHLESS |LISTEN THIS EVERYDAY AND CHANGE YOUR LIFE - Duration: 10:18. I might be talking about a fluffy pink stole made of ostrich feathers. Friday, 11 October 2013 Argument from Time and Contingency - Refuted Craig’s crafty (though futile) effort to slither a course between these two fallacies demonstrates that he is mindful of his predicament. Whichever I’m talking about, I should try to be clear. Contingency Argument. To say that something is contingent means that it is not necessary. It couldn’t have been any other way.”, Amy: “Why not? This is probably the most important passage in … It is the belief that "everything happens for a reason", that there is actually sufficient (and, indeed, good!) I shall show in this paper that this refutation, while it is frequently taken to be valid,' is in fact fallacious. The structure of an argument goes from initial premise to conclusion. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gtfVds8Kn4s. Definition 1 emphasizes our uncertainty about whether the contingent entity will exist: the entity’s existence is conditional. Yet these efficient causes could be implemented, as far as we know, only by force carrier particles that cannot exceed the speed of light and would therefore manifest as a temporal causal chain. . (So-called final causes are more accurately identified as motives.) Peter Kreeft presents the contingency argument by way of a homey analogy. Science can only show what happens in the actual world. We all know that God is taken by most people in Craig’s audience to be a conscious being, whereas “immaterial cause,” to the extent that it has meaning, doesn’t imply any such thing. Yet Craig commits himself to a far more extravagant conjecture and thereby makes a far more egregious mistake by saying that premise 1 supports the speculation that the cosmos has an immaterial cause. You would probably think I was being purposely deceitful. The efficient cause of the painter’s sunburn was a defect in her sunscreen. My writing differs from Aquinas’s writing not only in volume, but also in tone. It makes no sense to cry out, “Ooh, I found a material cause! It is based on a false premise. Otherwise, all deductive arguments would be fallacious. Craig is arguing that if there’s a cause of M, then (1) M or Not-M is the cause, (2) M is not the cause; therefore, Not-M is the cause. No, I’m not. Aquinas, a member of this order, spent most of his life writing an estimated 8 to 11 million words. Craig himself, in defense of premise 1, provides examples only of material causes, never of immaterial causes. But if you say God’s nature is contingent on something else, then God is a contingent entity. The analogy’s exploitation of scientific illiteracy exemplifies a much broader principle manifest throughout apologetics: Every argument for the supernatural realm is rooted in ignorance of the natural realm. The argument against the existence of God offered by this gentleman is not a valid one. A lot of people conflate the argument from contingency with the so-called “cosmological” argument (a.k.a. That something must not have been a contingent thing, but a necessary thing. An informal fallacy, in contrast, can’t be detected by examining the structure of the argument. The debate starts with a lengthy discussion of the Cosmological Argument.Copleston presents a version of the argument based on contingency, which is based on Aquinas' 'Third Way' and Leibniz's Principle of Sufficient Reason.Russell responds by questioning whether necessary existence (aseity) is a … Sometimes it’s called petitio principii or circular reasoning. What we call today the Kalam Cosmological Argument, was first made by Aristotle and then by Islamic scholars in the 9th century. The conclusion of his argument (statement 5) is that immaterial causation (God) exists. Therefore, the universe has an explanation of its existence (from 1 and 3). Craig, however, doesn’t want to talk only about material causes. it is contingent, as opposed to necessary), we then need some explanation of why it does exist. The Modal Cosmological Argument, also known as the Argument from Contingency, suggests that because the universe might not have existed (i.e. In other words, if we trace back through all the causes within the material realm, and if we encounter the very first material cause, which we can call M, then if we find the cause of M, that cause must be immaterial. Explain the premises of the argument of contingency. The first argument that I would like to consider with you is the argument from contingency. To the pragmatic atheistmany of these arguments remain unpersuasive, ranging from defining something into existence, to at best arguing for some form of … Craig is mired in a catch-22 predicament. For perspective, 10 million words is equivalent to over 60 books the size of the one you’re reading now. The posts here describe conversations with Apologists & what I regard as their fallacious arguments. True, but so is God. Notice that the weakness of this argument would be less apparent if I strike all references to efficient boas, snakes, and stoles and use only the word boas, by which I still mean efficient boas: We have seen boas within the park; therefore, boas exist outside the park. Craig is speaking of the Kalām argument, not contingency argument, but the objections and defenses largely overlap. From the The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, a newer generation of philosophical arguments have been released to apologists. But if you say God’s nature is contingent on something else, then God is a contingent entity. That tells us nothing of theological significance. The argument against the existence of God offered by this gentleman is not a valid one. I've been thinking more and more about the Cosmological Argument lately and I noticed there was a recent thread on it in this forum. All Rights Reserved. Cosrx Salicylic Acid Daily Gentle Cleanser Review,
Bdm Main Quest,
Marvel Premiere Featuring Iron Fist,
Millet Ski Pants,
Baby Gherkin Pickles,
Insurance Sales Agents Salary,
Whale Template Sewing,
Calea Chocolate Cake Recipe,
Nivea Express Hydration Body Lotion 400ml,
Project Portfolio Example For Interview,
Makita Circular Saw Parts Diagram,
Nikon P1000 Bird Photography,
Heinz Seriously Good Mayonnaise,
Esper Stoneblade Legacy,
" />